When we ask here more
specifically about life, we
find that neither the tradition's principle
of identity, nor
Levinas' phenomenological uniqueness
offer adequate
accounts of how life's individualizations take shape and duration.
Identity bears only tautological witness to the distinguishability
of instances of form; and uniqueness gives no direct correlation
with reality's objective aspect.
|
|
Yet uniqueness does have a place in the tale of life's evolutionary
individuations, for exposure and
expression are increasing ingredients of the sociality through
which more individualized life appears and survives... 
|
|
...have
you read Frans De Waal's
Bonobo; The Forgotten Ape?
...whose very brains
convolute with the overflow
of their afferent cortical canvas of sense.
|
|
neurobiology notes |
Similarly, we can indirectly
give place in our
understanding of life's integral individuations to the other
movements of transcendence named in parts (b) and (c
) of Section VI: brainwise too, with respect to VI (b),
efferent 'final common pathways' channel purposeful performance,
integrating contexts of potentials - stretching and pushing
patterns of potential difference into the shapes of thresholds that
sequence moments: moments whose sequence can reach only so far in
time as the distinctness of those moments in support of their
context's potentials. Concepts, from this perspective, are species
of such momentary distinction, heirs of the conformation of purpose
to the kaleidoscopic contingencies of physical potentials.
Generality, the power of concepts, is secured through the promise
of concepts to function as schemata holding open time as a horizon
of activity, effectively as blinders that narrow and extend the aim
of sight for the purpose of directing motion. The most
concretely universal concept, by this, would have to be Nietzsche's
fictional
Zarathustra's fictional 'Eternal Return', which reaches so far in
time that Becoming and Being appear indistinguishable, but at the
cost of excluding everything potentially new.
|
|
 Finally, in the
case of VI (c), meaning presupposes
memory, while memory bears clearly on factors such as brain size
and life-span which strongly correlate with individuation among
living creatures. Moreover, the intrications of meaning with
metaphor perhaps finds substrate in the evolving nervous system's
increasingly ubiquitous reliance upon interneuronal
inhibition; as if life in this way cultivates backgrounds of
quieting where echoes from different times can be heard together,
on a par, and so emergently open experience into such spaces of
equivocal and polyvalent referentiality as draw out singular
meanings - threads from the tapestry of time - while sustaining
time's differences as internal to meaning's ceaseless spinning of
itself from metaphor's contextualizations.
|
|
That the above three factors
can be named, for
example as sense and concept
and meaning, and
that they can be emphasized, in how we have turned them, as of
preeminent  importance
for taking upon ourselves the mystery of things, still leaves great
puzzlement as to the terms by which they cleave together.
Nietzsche warns us. 'At the point where our ignorance begins,
and beyond which we no longer see
anything, we put
a word.' That cheap solution here would be to
accord all
worldly existence for experience a composite
character. Buddhist
doctrine allows
us to dignify such an option quite considerably. And when we point
to the word 'composition' as also naming artistic labors, we
purport to further persuasively analogize life with music and even
more generally with art in its craft of forming symbols.
|
|
The tract
of everything
would
by a
good discourser
lose some
life which action's
self
was tongue
to.
|
We also might hope that as
each of the three factors attain better description, transforming
the language that they share, their inextricability will become
self-evident: for example, Steiner
mused
that thinking, feeling, and willing were more mixed within each
other than he earlier had realized. But do we then remain in the
dark on whether we should say we are citing words or things? An
option cagier than resting with words would be
instead to go
with , 'We have already grown beyond
whatever
we have words for.' Which Nietzsche also supplies. In any
case, asserting
the composite nature of things makes possible no more than names on
the marquee for what we should expect to be exceptionally
action-packed adventure.
|
|
|
When now previewing what we can only present as moving pictures,
the attraction will be scene supplying the place of individuation's
worldly appearance: a scene cast for character.
An
idea also important to Kant, 'Character' in Bergson
finds
articulation as how a whole appears in expressions that are
evidently partial. Taking character as our scene, we aspire to
encounter individuation in how it is implicated in
issues of integrity.
As musical changes hold their season in meshing paraphrase of note
structures, so life's circumstance poses life questions of
integrity. Patterns interfere with each other and condense or
rarify distributions of potential differences. The name for the
shape of such interactions is phase; and even while
phase
locally seasons thresholds in their fragility or volatility, as
shape the distribution of phase projects the very
patterns
whose interference it 
transacts. So from how life
wears, life finds
a familiar spirit ranging in differential sensitivities beyond the
relevance of immediacy.
A life exists in its sea of troubles; fluctuating topographies of
potential differences which rareify and condense, their thresholds
canalised as retardations and advancements of sensitivity. The
condensations, in bearing inward, in posing discontinuities, often
take origin even from the structural consequences of the
rarefactions attentioning the gradations of a life's sensitivities
beyond itself.
Time doth
transfix the flourish
set on youth, and delves parallels
in beauty's
brow.
|
Form for life expresses measures of ignorance and attunement (oft
bound together as habit). In wearing thin, life
finds
semaphores in the waves which break around it, in the fall of a
sparrow, in peculiar emulations of Bell's
theorem; but at apparent cost. Life
exists as
tearings and mendings, and life's patchwork negotiates against
taking its form as expressing a principle of identity, though not
as marks of character. Character especially when tearing
and
mending can converge and superpose as exposure and expression, for
then part and whole wear together, an option of providential
economy.
|
|
In taking bearings
toward wholeness, lives
adopt their characters; a life's identity takes place and local
habitation not in giving itself a name, but as a
direction
of development, a strange journey in an ever more familiar
landscape, an unfolding through metaphor of
meaning. ‡
Then again, development
as direction, before it finds itself as character, sends itself as play,
but the reader should not expect
to find more now than
- ' characters from a play'. For
now we spin
our wheels (cf., however, Section VIII, above).
Faced with the prospect of
traversing a
labyrinth the like of which we have in trying to example life's
composition, Nietzsche
finally opted for yet another 'easy out';
'The organism is governed in such a way that the mechanical world as
well as the spiritual world can
provide only a symbolical
explanation.'‡
We too were at
least prepared to leave it at that - perhaps we should still be
thought to have done so - except that the worrisome turn to another
century approaches, and we might find deserved reproach from
physics, biology, and thinking, for not trying to give full weight
to what they have brought into the one now passing.
|
|
Love
is too
young
to know
what
conscience
is,
yet
who knows not
conscience is born of
love?
|
Nietzsche
characterized
consciousness as the actuality of
the possibility of a more comprehensive kind of body. And as we see
the Earth's ecology and economy knit itself together as determined
by human thought and action, one form of such a 'more
comprehensive' body takes shape before us. There is an
urgency that we find a matrix for the activities of mind which will
help shape the world's body in the image of that 'wisdom of love'
which has somehow, from long ago already given us a Nature before
whose wonders we remain as children.
|
|
Love, one of Philosophy's namesakes, is always both difficult and
easy. Love has always, too, been motive for the kinds of thinking
which here have been discussed, though thinking has yet rarely
discussed love. Thinking's difficulty - a labor of love - gives
openings for thinking's renewal which, from time to time, arrive as
grace - sans effort - the sort of thing we find sometimes in
musical performance; a transmutation of painstaking practice and
attention into free breath and fresh artistic vision.
|
|
The greatest loves are the
longest loves and the
loves for what most is different from ourselves. Each of these
offer the full measure of love's difficulty and love's grace. And
though our world brings us these two challenges as near at odds,
and threatens us with a devil's choice between them, Mind holds
open the chance to unfold their conjuncture.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
neurobiology notes
Afferent canvas of
sense / efferent
'final common pathway': topologically the afferent system, derived
from the - dorsal - alar plates of the embryological neural tube is
characterized by one-to-many mappings from lower to higher neural
levels - hence mostly informationally phase dispersing, while the
efferent system derives from the - ventral - basal plate and
exhibits many-to-one mappings from higher to lower levels which
converge phase information.
Neural inhibition: within the afferent system, higher levels
increasingly originate inhibitory potentials relative to afferent
and efferent lower levels, and these typically have durations of
influence typically many times longer longer than excitatory
potentials.
|
mechanical /
spiritual Quoted in
Eric Blondel's Nietzsche:
The Body and
Culture - Philosophy as a Philological Genealogy
, page 204.
|
'When we ask here more
specifically
about life' This
entire rondo-finale
owes itself to a panoply of influences not cited explicitly within
it. Among these are
A.N. Whitehead, Susanne Langer,
Gregory Bateson,
David Bohm, Roger
Penrose, and Paul Ricoeur.
But also
Chaos Theory, its Anthroposophical prophet - Theodor Schwenk, the
visionary embryologists C.H. Waddington
for his 'chreods' and Erich
Blechschmidt for his incredibly concrete dynamic
descriptions,
Ilya Prigogine for his
thermodynamic
'dissipative structures', Lancelot Law Whyte
for his 'coordinative conditions', R. Buckminster Fuller
for the principle of tensegrity -
complementation of local compression with global tension, and
Hartwig Kuhlenbeck;
perhaps the last
exponent of the Jena-Heidelberg school of Comparative Morphology -
founded by Goethe - for his
many volume
The Central Nervous System of Vertebrates.
|
|
|