Dilthey's
hermeneutical descriptions were as much at pains to constitute the
process by which different peoples' experience is woven between
them into a world of meaning as
Husserl's were to constitute
individual experience
by exhibiting the lamination of sensations, intentions and
significations. But while Dilthey often waxed eloquent, virtually
intoxicated by the flow of life-experience to which he had set his
mind in thrall, the life of Husserl's mind seems an exercise in
sobriety. This great soliloquist and practitioner of doubt, like
Hamlet, repeatedly urges 'once more remove' to his friends so that
his pristine new foundations for philosophy may be set on ground
not haunted by inconclusive spirits from the past.
Husserl's
insistence that
First Philosophy begin from the most indispensable and most present
kind of knowing was part of the last important effort to cast
philosophy as the 'science of sciences.' Little philosophy
subsequently grew directly on the ground Husserl staked out: though
it may have been sterile enough to serve science, its infertility
for subsequent thinking raises questions about whether thinking
should ally itself with the methods and goals of the sciences. So
while Husserl pursued his phenomenology in the spirit of a science,
his great influence upon subsequent thinking comes from how what he
regarded as evidence
differs from what the sciences
need to
assume.
For science, evidence is
found where
phenomena can be reduced by analysis to their simplest 'building
blocks'. Husserl's reduction, on the other hand,
was toward
the usually overlooked evidence given by what is most familiar -
the constitutive acts which make awareness whole and which all
experience relies on to give it sense. Thinkers here under
discussion usually found with Husserl common cause in emphasizing
such evidence of whole experience over that derived in pieces by
analysis.
Though
Dilthey
and
Husserl
may not have identified
their own restless involvements with methodology as a
'transformative practice' in the spirit of
Nietzsche or
Steiner,
some kinds of kinship are evident. Their common quest was Mind's
more complete incarnation in the world of human life. And as
Steiner and Nietszche were not satisfied with the sort of
'conversion' or 'leap of faith' which had been the object of many
earlier kinds of transformative practices, so Husserl and Dilthey
did not allow themselves to be guided by the anticipation of a
final philosophic system capable of solving the problems they had
posed. All four maintained thinking as an open path.