As we begin to bring this
model to bear, it
holds, in the way of thinking's emergent tendencies, a new kind of
direct involvement in temporality in the place of the top layer,
and a new role for the symbolic and metaphorical aspects of meaning
where we identify a middle layer. The bottom layer too, which in
one aspect we describe as productive of facts, has a distinctive
character in our time; the shapes of facts being given increasingly
in explicit accord with specific techniques of inquiry and
instrumentalities of action.
|
|
 If such a model
can help us envisage
a future for thinking, it should also be able to shed light on its
past. Indeed, even when we look backward we can discern the regions
which differentiate more fully in our time: There seems always to
have been polarization between the objective in the direction of
our bottom layer and the subjective toward what we call the top
layer. But in philosophy the zone between, which in its dynamism of
forming symbols Langer
recognized as feeling, has been treated more or less as an
embarrassment threatening to contaminate the universality of both
objects and subject. Hence feeling has been a thing philosophy has
mostly tried to extirpate from thinking in the name of a 'higher
subject' and more real objects.
|
|
O
place, O
form,
how
often dost thou
with thy case,
thy habit,
wrench
awe from fools
and tie the wiser souls
to
thy false seeming.
|
By the late Nineteenth century
most of what we meet in that zone between the subjective and the
objective are the barren supporting structures of ideologically
rooted 'paradigms'. These typically had used logics which
presupposed particular values to fix a form belonging to facts on
the one hand, and similarly directed reflections on self-experience
to fix the kind of unity belonging to the subject, on the other. In
between, meanings become mere examples of principles. Numerous
reductionisms in our own time still follow this overall pattern.
Where people are dieted to any such 'official culture',
totalitarianisms precede decadence and decay.
|
|
|
Changes in thinking which
begin to
redifferentiate that kind of polarization of mind show up in the
vicinity of the transition into the twentieth century: Bergson
identifies our prospective
'top layer' when he argues that the essence of subjectivity should
be recognized not as an experience of identity reducible to unity
but rather as an experience of pure duration bringing into creative
play the qualities of experience.
|
|
 |
Relative to a 'bottom layer'
of objective facts,
despite William James
'pragmatic' protestations, logic and positivism at first intensify
their claims on the whole of the life of the mind but subsequently
crumble and are abandoned as the implications of investigations
like quantum physics and Kurt Godel's
famous
mathematical theorem sink in, leaving us with the contemporary
instrumental approach to the constitution of a layer of
'facts'.
|
|
There's matter in
these
sighs,
these profound
heaves,
you must translate.
'Tis fit we
understand
them.
|
With respect
to our
emergent 'middle layer', even before the century's turn, Dilthey
courageously worked to
develop his entire philosophy within a domain of perceptually
active feeling which comprehensively informs both thinking and
willing. For Dilthey feeling serves as the raw material from which
experience shapes its entire world of meaning. Nietzsche's transvaluations
alike
point to how forms of feeling - symbols - are charged with
polyvalent meaning.
|
|
To
associate Will, even as bridged by a notion of instrumentality,
with objectivity and facts may seem incongruous. But that
connection expresses important conditions: Facere,
fact's
Latin root, means 'to make' (as in manufacture):
will is
proven only through what is made objective. The main challenge here
is attributing the conceptual aspect of objectivity
to our
model's bottom layer instead of its top. This does foreshadow a
drastic reorientation of the tradition in how we will subsequently
situate the basic factors of experience. The interim fluidity of
nomenclature is purchased from my reliance here on a model. Models
are frameworks whose entities retain the status of conventions
subject to adjustment for the purpose of describing
function. |
|
And Rudolf
Steiner even articulates the same sort of threefold
perspective
we are suggesting: In his topography of experience, Steiner
situates feeling as between thinking
and
willing; between what we are calling at this point the
subjective and the instrumental. Moreover Steiner emphasized how
his time had seen this aspect of experience dangerously weakened
and undervalued. In our own time we find the polyvalence of the
symbolic adequately clarified on the one hand in its temporality by Ricoeur,
and on the other
in how the course of feeling 'rhythmically' binds objective and
subjective principles to produce symbolic forms which stand
intermediate and mediating between the subjective and the
objective, by Langer.
|
|

As we now turn our three layer model to look toward the future of
mind, we meet the necessity of again assessing Heidegger's contribution. His
work
undoubtedly offers us a kind of 'top layer' where involvement in
representations no longer displace thinking from its elemental
temporality. Yet Heidegger's assignment of thinking to the question
concerning the meaning of Being invokes a unitary
principle,
both in terms of the thinker's self-experience and in terms of the
truth of Being toward which thinking aspires.
The capabilities of
Heidegger's kind of thinking help make sense of thinking's
past: his requiem for the cathedrals of philosophy shifted thinking
into temporality as if possessing philosophy with its predestined
after-life. But Heidegger is of little direct help in answering to
a future where mind's entire productivity requires integration. For
this, thinking must leave behind
not only its
fixation in representation but also its ideal of
unity.
|
|
In our
evolutionary model, diversity within mind's lower layers requires
diversity at the top as well. Nor should we really find this
surprising: Hannah Arendt
(1906-1975),
following Aristotle,
reminds us that
thinking follows the pattern of conversation‡,
and so what should seem surprising is
that for so long it has been approached almost entirely apart from
any syntax of engagement with others' experience, and instead held
to be the crowning act of self-sufficient self-identity.
Furthermore, because thinking is rooted in temporality, in
duration, if we would think truthfully we should have our thinking
heed, in all of its beginnings the overlap which Whitehead
tells us belongs to
entities whose boundaries include duration.
|
|
|
Thinking has
characteristically referred itself
to a unitary subject. In this it locates itself on the basis of its
end results - concepts - both in the aspect of
their powers
of unification and in how they in general offer experience the
kinds of 'handles' which persuade it of things' reality among other
things. But subjectivity is not a thing among other things,  especially for itself, and it unfitting
for it to try and fit itself
with handles for its
own use on itself. Likewise, the subject's pretense to unity: the
skill of concepts is more exclusion than inclusion - so a subject
cut from the cloth of its concepts is one who dresses its self in
equine blinders.
|
|
It is the case that the
general question our model seems poised to pose with respect to
changing Mind revolves around mind's involvement with
multiplicities and pluralities, what James considered 'the most central
of philosophic
problems'. Traditional philosophy often regards
multiplicity
as an illusion which it is the task of higher orders of thinking to
resolve into unity.
|
|
 |
Even
when we look at
our model we can find grounds for that unifying
inclination: In the lower layer, regardless of the realities it
addresses, instrumental reason is deployed in rounds of operations
- systems of relations - which maintain consistency and which can
be articulated as a unifying set of principles. In the middle layer
we would feel great diversity of meanings, but each one makes its
claim on the basis of offering experience of its wholeness - which
we can then interpret as common between the different kinds of
wholeness, as Cassirer did.
In the top
layer we find each subject separately experiencing its own
identity, but that principle of identity is itself in common and
can be interpreted as a window on the oneness of Being.
|
|
Let your reason
serve
to make
the truth
appear where
it
seems hid,
and hide
the
false
seems
true.
|
However, by turning the
whole demonstration
around, the pretense of unity is again lost. Here, instrumental
reason through its systems overlooks and conceals the real
diversity of the events it manipulates; in the middle, symbolic
thinking makes wholes only because its metaphorical codings
require closure; and at the top, self-experience testifies not to
an underlying unity but to unavoidable alienation. Similar critical
inversions are well represented by current trends in Continental
thought such as semiotics and deconstructionism.
|
|

|
Such inversions often
suffice to dethrone the
priorities and orientation of traditional thinking, but offer
little positive ground through which plurality can
invest
mind from top to bottom with a truer correspondence to life. James' and the
later Wittgenstein's
cultivation of distinctions which individualize experience in the
light of lived contextual relevance is broadly helpful, but perhaps
because they do not venture a typology of learning (for example, as
may be found in Bateson's
work), their work does not conveniently reflect the kind of
'layered' differentiation of Mind we here desire. We are guided,
then, by the resurgent 'middle layer' of feelings and symbols
pioneered by Dilthey
and
developed by Ricoeur
and Langer,
for here our model's
need for real variations comes closest to satisfaction, but whence
comes a renewal for mind's 'two other layers'?
We do have a pair of contemporary thinkers who make significant
advances here toward grounding mind in genuine plurality. One,
Gilles Deleuze, explores
plurality in its
'objective' articulations, while the other, Emmanuel Levinas, works from the side we
have called
'subjective' - thinking's temporality. The implications of their
work allow us to complete our reorientation of the tradition, and
so will make it possible to more coherently situate some of the
issues raised in Sections VI through VIII. But these two thinkers
are among the most challenging we have encountered, and their
treatment will be less extensive than they unquestionably
deserve.
|
|
|
|
|
|
The
error of our eye directs
our mind.
What error leads must err.
|
-Troilus
and Cressida, V, ii,
112 |
O
place, O form,
how often dost thou with thy case, thy habit,
Wrench awe from fools
and tie the wiser souls to thy false seeming.
|
-
Hamlet, IV, i, 1 |
There's
matter in these
sighs, these profound heaves,
You must translate. 'Tis fit we understand them.
|
-Measure
for Measure, V, i,
65 |
Let
your reason serve
to make the truth appear where it seems hid,
and hide the false seems true.
|
-
Measure for Measure, II, iv,
12 |
|